Central Events in Mathematics
Year | Country | Event |
---|---|---|
600 BCE | Greece | Thales founds abstract geometry and deductive mathematics with the “Thales Proposition” (triangles over the diameter of a circle are right-angled), the oldest theorem of occidental mathematics. |
520 BCE | Greece | The Pythagorean theorem appears, allegedly proved by Pythagoras. |
420 BCE | Greece | Hippias of Elis discovers the quadratix, the first known curve that cannot be constructed with a straightedge and compass. |
350 BCE | Greece | Menaechmus makes the first known attempt to investigate the geometry of the cone. |
300 BCE | Alexandria | Euclid’s Elements synthesizes and systematizes knowledge of geometry. |
260 BCE | Greece | Archimedes calculates the first known value for π. |
250 BCE | Greece | Conon of Samos discovers the curve known as the spiral of Archimedes. |
232 BCE | Greece | Apollonius of Perga’s Conicorum presents a systematic treatment of the principles of conics, introducing the terms parabola, ellipse, and hyperbola. |
50 | Greece | Hero of Alexandria discovers the formula for expressing the area of a triangle in terms of its sides. |
98 | Greece | Menelaus gives the first definition of a spherical triangle and theorems on congruence of spherical triangles, founding spherical trigonometry. |
250 | Greece | Diophantus discovers solutions to certain equations, known as Diophantine equations, that represent the beginnings of algebra. |
490 | China | Zu Chongzhi calculates that π lies between 3.1415926 and 3.1415927, by far the most accurate estimate of π to that time. |
500 | India | Aryabhatiya summarizes Indian mathematical knowledge. |
700 | India | Over the course of 8C, a full and consistent use of zero develops. |
810 | Persia | Al-Khwarizmi’s Hisab al-Jabr W’al-Musqabalah gives methods for solving all equations of the first and second degree with positive roots, synthesizes Babylonian with Greek methods, and is the origin of the word algebra. |
870 | Persia | Thabit ibn Qurra translates Greek mathematical texts into Arabic. His translations will become the major source for European knowledge of Greek mathematics. |
1100 | Persia | Omar Khayyam is the first to solve some cubic equations. |
1120 | England | Adelhard of Bath translates an Arabic version of Euclid’s Elements into Latin, introducing Euclid to Europe. |
1202 | Italy | Leonardo Fibonacci’s Liber Abaci awakens Europe to the advantages of Arabic numerals and computation. |
1350 | France | Nicole Oresme anticipates coordinate geometry with a plot of time against velocities. |
1360 | France | Nicole Oresme introduces fractional exponents. |
1464 | Germany | Regiomontus’s De Triangulis Omnimodus is the first systematic European work on trigonometry as a subject divorced from astronomy. |
1491 | Italy | Filippo Calandri publishes an account of the modern method of long division. |
1494 | Italy | Luca Pacioli’s Summa de Arithmetica presents an overview of mathematics handed down from the Middle Ages, becoming one of the most influential mathematics books of its time. It is also the first book to discuss double-entry bookkeeping. |
1525 | Austria | Christoff Rudolff's Die Coss introduces the square root symbol and introduces decimal fractions. |
1535 | Italy | Tartaglia discovers a general method for solving cubic equations. |
1545 | Italy | Girolamo Cardano's Ars Magna is the first book of modern mathematics. |
1551 | Germany | Rheticus prepares tables of standard trigonometric functions, defining trigonometric functions for the first time as ratios of the sides of a right triangle rather than defining them relative to the arcs of circles. |
1557 | Wales | Robert Recorde introduces an elongated version of the equal sign into mathematics, and introduces the plus and minus signs into English. |
1572 | Italy | Rafael Bombelli introduces the first consistent theory of imaginary numbers. |
1580 | France | Francois Viete introduces a precise analytic definition of π. |
1585 | Netherlands | Simon Stevin’s De Thiende presents a systematic account of how to use decimal fractions. |
1591 | France | Francois Viete introduces the systematic use of algebraic symbols. |
1613 | Italy | Pietro Cataldi develops methods of working with continued fractions. |
1614 | Scotland | John Napier’s Mirifici Logarithmorum Cationis Descriptio introduces logarithms. |
1631 | England | William Oughtred's Ciavis Mathematicae summarizes the status of arithmetic and algebra, employing extensive mathematical symbolism. |
1635 | Italy | Francesco Cavalieri’s Geometria Indivisibilibus Continuorum expounds a method of using “indivisibles” that foreshadows integral calculus. |
1637 | France | Pierre de Fermat states his Last Theorem. |
1637 | Netherlands | Rene Descartes’ “La Geometrie,” an appendix to Discours de la Methode, founds analytic geometry. |
1637 | Netherlands | Rene Descartes’ “La Geometrie” introduces exponents and square root signs. |
1638 | France | Pierre de Fermat achieves major progress toward differential calculus, determining maxima and minima by procedures used today. |
1640 | France | Pierre de Fermat founds number theory through his work on the properties of whole numbers. |
1648 | France | Girard Desargues’s Maniere Universelle de Mr. Desargues pour Pratiquer la Perspective contains Desargues’s theorem, founding projective geometry. |
1654 | France | Pierre de Fermat and Blaise Pascal found probability theory with methods for judging the likelihood of outcomes in games of dice. |
1654 | France | Blaise Pascal’s “Traite du Triangle Arithmetique” analyzes the properties of the arithmetical triangle. |
1655 | England | John Wallis’s Arithmetica Infinitorium introduces concepts of limit and negative and fractional exponents, along with the symbol for infinity. |
1657 | Netherlands | Christiaan Huygens introduces the concept of mathematical expectation into probability theory |
1662 | England | John Graunt’s Natural and Political Observations Made upon the Bills of Mortality is the first significant use of vital statistics. |
1668 | Belgium | Nicolus Mercator calculates the area under a curve, using analytical geometry. |
1668 | Scotland | James Gregory introduces a precursor of the fundamental theorem of calculus, expressed geometrically. |
1669 | England, Germany | Isaac Newton’s De Analysi per Aequationes Numero Terminorum Infinitas presents the first systematic account of the calculus, independently developed by Gottfried Leibniz. |
1670 | England | Isaac Barrow discovers a method of tangents essentially equivalent to those used in differential calculus. |
1676 | England | Isaac Newton formally states the binomial theorem. |
1685 | England | John Wallis introduces the first graphical representation of complex numbers. |
1687 | England | Isaac Newton’s Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematical appears, representing the origin of modern applied mathematics. |
1693 | England | Edmond Halley prepares the first detailed mortality tables. |
1704 | England | Isaac Newton’s Enumberatio Linearum Tertii Ordinis describes the properties of cubic curves. |
1713 | Switzerland | Jakob Bernoulli’s Ars Conjectandi contains Bernoulli’s theorem, that any degree of statistical accuracy can be obtained by sufficiently increasing the observations, thereby also representing the first application of calculus to probability theory. |
1715 | England | Brook Taylor’s Methodus Incrementorum Directa et Inversa introduces the calculus of finite differences. |
1718 | England | Abraham de Moivre’s Doctrine of Chances is the first systematic treatise on probability theory. |
1720 | Scotland | Colin Maclaurin’s Geometrica Organica describes the general properties of planar curves. |
1731 | France | Alexis Clairaut’s Recherches sur les Conrbes a Double Courbure is a pioneering study of the differential geometry of space curves. |
1733 | Italy | Girolamo Saccheri’s Euclides ab Omni Naevo Vindicatus inadvertently lays the foundation for non-Euclidean geometry |
1770 | France | Johann Lambert demonstrates that both π and π² are irrational. |
1795 | Germany | Carl Gauss proves the law of quadratic reciprocity. |
1796 | Germany | Carl Gauss discovers a method for constructing a heptadecagon with compass and straightedge and demonstrates that an equilateral heptagon could not be constructed the same way, constituting the only notable advance in classic geometry since ancient Greece. |
1797 | Norway | Caspar Wessel introduces the first geometric representation of complex numbers employing the x-axis as the axis of reals and the y-axis as the axis of imaginaries. |
1799 | France | Gaspard Monge introduces advances in projecting three-dimensional objects onto two-dimensional planes, founding descriptive geometry. |
1799 | Germany | Carl Gauss presents a new and rigorous proof of the fundamental theorem of algebra. |
1801 | Germany | Carl Gauss’s Disquisitiones Arithmeticae expands number theory to embrace algebra, analysis, and geometry. |
1803 | France | Lazare Carnot’s Geometrie de Position revives and extends projective geometry. |
1807 | France | Jean Fourier introduces Fourier’s theorem and the beginnings of Fourier analysis. |
1810 | France | Joseph Gergonne's Annales de Mathematiques Pures et Appliques is one of the first periodicals devoted to mathematics and becomes highly influential. |
1812 | France | Pierre Laplace's Theorie Analytiquc des Probabilities introduces the Laplace transform and expands the power of probability theory. |
1813 | France | Simeon Poisson derives the Poisson distribution. |
1817 | Czechoslovakia | Bernardus Bolzano develops calculus using a continuous function, dispensing with infinitesimals. |
1822 | France | Fourier’s Theorie Analytiquc de la Chaleur gives a full presentation of Fourier’s dimensional analysis, using mass, time, and length as fundamental dimensions that must be expressed in consistent units. |
1822 | France | Jean Poncelet’s Traite des Proprietes Projectives des Figures serves as a foundation of modern geometry. |
1823 | Hungary | Janos Bolyai develops the first consistent system of non-Euclidean geometry, but publication is delayed until 1832. |
1824 | Norway | Niels Abel proves the impossibility of a general solution for quintic equations. |
1825 | France | Adrien Legendre’s Traite des Fonctions Elliptiques et des Integrales Euleriennes presents a systematic account of his theory of elliptic integrals. |
1825 | France | Jean Poncelet and Joseph Gergonne develop the first clear expression of the principle of duality in geometry. |
1825 | Norway | Niels Abel creates elliptic functions and discovers their double periodicity. |
1829 | Russia | Nikolai Lobachevsky introduces hyperbolic geometry, replacing Euclid’s parallel postulate and founding one of the most important systems of non-Euclidean geometry |
1830 | France | Evariste Galois develops group theory, critical later for quantum mechanics. |
1843 | Ireland | William Hamilton introduces quaternions (algebra with hyper-complex numbers). |
1844 | Germany | Hermann Grassmann’s theory of “extended magnitude” generalizes quaternions, creating an algebra of vectors. |
1847 | England | George Boole’s The Mathematical Analysis of Logic introduces Boolean algebra, systematically applying algebraic operations to logic. |
1851 | Germany | Bernhard Riemann introduces topological considerations into the study of complex functions and lays the basis for Riemann surfaces. |
1854 | Germany | Bernhard Riemann’s Uber die Hypothesen Welche der Geometrie zu Grande Liegen introduces a new non-Euclidean geometry and accelerates the acceptance and potential utility of non-Euclidean geometries. |
1857 | England | Arthur Cayley introduces the algebra of matrices. |
1872 | Germany | Felix Klein’s “Erlanger Programm” calls for geometry to be based on groups of transformations. |
1872 | Germany | Richard Dedekind introduces theory that any rational or irrational number can be defined in terms of rationals. |
1873 | France | August Hermite proves that e is transcendental. |
1874 | Germany | Georg Cantor’s first formal publication on set theory founds the field. |
1881 | USA | Josiah Gibbs’s Elements of Vector Analysis introduces a system of vectors in three dimensions. |
1882 | Germany | Carl Lindemann proves that π is transcendental. |
1883 | Germany | Georg Cantor introduces transfinite set theory. |
1884 | Sweden | Sonya Kovalevskaya demonstrates that certain kinds of Abelian integrals can be expressed in terms of simpler elliptic integrals. |
1895 | France | Henri Poincare’s Analysis Situs effectively founds topology (although a few theorems of topology had already been proved). |
1899 | Germany | David Hilbert’s Grundlagen der Geometrie establishes the basic axiomatic-formalist approach to systematizing mathematics, initiated by compactly deriving a formal axiomatic model for Euclid’s geometry. |
1902 | France | Henri Lebesgue introduces a new theory for integrating discontinuous functions. |
1906 | France | Maurice Frechet introduces a geometry of abstract spaces and the concepts of separability and completeness. |
1910 | England | Bertrand Russell’s and Alfred Whitehead’s Principia Mathematica represents the best, though flawed, attempt to establish mathematics as branch of logic. |
1931 | Austria | Kurt Godel demonstrates that any formal system strong enough to include the laws of arithmetic is either incomplete or inconsistent. |
1934 | Russia | Aleksander Gelfond and T. Schneider demonstrate that an irrational power of an algebraic number other than zero or one is transcendental. |
1936 | England | Alan Turing’s “On Computable Numbers” develops the hypothetical Turing machine as a method of determining what kinds of mathematical results can be proved. |